Wednesday, October 9, 2013

Market demand and the pricing decision


The market demand curve is important for business in two practical ways. First,
the decision to invest in expanded production capacity or in a marketing campaign
requires a close analysis of the expected growth of demand over time.
Second, the firm’s pricing decision depends on the nature of the demand curve
for the firm’s products. The pricing decision, of course, is not determined solely
by demand-side considerations – the company’s cost function and profit objectives,
and the reaction of competitors, have also to be taken into account – but
demand analysis plays a crucial part in the decision.

What is a ‘rational’ consumer?

The theory of demand explains how an individual responds to changes in key
economic variables such as prices and income. Five major assumptions about
consumer behaviour are made which elaborate on the hypothesis that consumers
are utility-maximisers.

These assumptions can be summarised under the headings
of comparability, non-satiation, consistency, convexity and independence.
These assumptions are reasonable, but nobody would claim that they provide a
completely realistic description of consumer behaviour. For example, when information is costly or difficult to acquire, we may not have sufficient knowledge to
rank preferences in a comprehensive and consistent manner. When consulting
professionals ,we are often unable to assess the quality of the services they are offering. The cost of acquiring information may lead the consumer to use a rule of thumb, or to follow the crowd. In such instances, recourse may be had to a less ambitious definition of rationality, such as ‘bounded’ rationality, whereby the consumer is assumed to be able to rank relevant,feasible and known options rather than all possible options.

Another problem arises when the utility derivable from the consumption of a
particular good or service is unknown or uncertain. Liberal and authoritarian
ideologies clash as to whether people are the best judges of their own interests in
such circumstances. For example, one reason often cited for supporting unpopular
innovative cultural products is that they will generate better returns in
the long run when people learn how to appreciate them. Such a ‘failure’ of appreciation on the part of the individual is ruled out by the assumption of comparability. Of course, the current preferences of the arts lobby may not be
necessarily more long-sighted than anybody else’s. The point is that people do not
always have a well-defined preference field. Tastes and preferences change over
time and the consequences of many decisions in economic life cannot be predicted. We try to weigh uncertain future benefits against certain present benefits.
The assumption of independent utilities has also been challenged. The opposite
proposition has been propounded: that much of the satisfaction we obtain
from the consumption of a particular good or service derives precisely from the
fact that others are unable to afford it. A large house in a good neighbourhood, or
a Rolls-Royce, yields much less utility if everyone has one. Similarly, we give
certain gifts because their cost is widely known and will be appreciated by the
receiver rather than because of any intrinsic usefulness of the gift. This type of
interdependence has important implications for pricing policy. ‘Position’, ‘gift’ or
‘snob’ goods may be positively, rather than negatively, related to price. Yet an
upward-sloping demand curve is an exceptional case and valid only within fairly
limited price ranges. At a price of £1 million each, even the demand for Rolls-
Royces will start to decline!

Keeping in mind these qualifications, the type of behaviour implied by the
above ‘rationality’ assumption is a reasonable approximation of reality.
Consumers weigh up alternatives, seek out and choose larger and better ‘baskets’
whenever possible. More consumption is better than less consumption. There is
sufficient independence of utilities to make economic growth and increased consumption a source of higher welfare. Formally, we can imagine each consumer as maximising utility, subject to a budget constraint .One interesting
result of this exercise shows that this idealised consumer will maximise utility
when the ratio of marginal utility to price is the same for all products consumed.


No comments:

Post a Comment